Cite Entry
September 9 2024
06:50 EDT
Bertrand Russell
SITE SEARCH ENGINE
|
Introduction to Philosophy
Bertrand Russell, "The Value of Philosophy"
Abstract: Russell distinguishes between the practical
and the philosophic mind, compares the relation of science and philosophy,
and traces the major goals of philosophy in chapter fifteen of his
Problems of Philosophy.
- How would you describe Russell's practical person?
- Why not live one's life as a practical person?
- What are the goals of philosophy?
- What does Russell think is the central value of
philosophical inquiry?
- Characterize the instinctive individual.
- What is "enlargement of self"?
- How does philosophical thinking relate to living
and acting in the world? Suggest some examples.
- Bertrand Russell (1872-1970) was a philosopher, mathematician, and
social reformer.
- A few biographical points are worth mentioning:
- Russell's parents died when he was a child; John Stuart Mill was
his godfather.
- He taught at Trinity College, Cambridge but was dismissed because
of his pacifist activities during World War I.
- He supported himself through lecturing and writing from 1919
until the late 1930's.
- He accepted a position of the City College of New York, but before
he could accept his duties, a judge denied his position saying
Russell was a threat to "public health, safety and morals."
- The Nobel
Prize Committee described him as "one of our time's
most brilliant spokesmen of rationality and humanity, and a
fearless champion of free speech and free thought in the West."
- Russell co-authored with Alfred North Whitehead, Principia
Mathematica. He had hoped to reduce mathematics to logic.
- Notes are arranged in response to the questions stated above in
reference to Russell's chapter "The Value of Philosophy"
edited from The Problems of Philosophy available on this site: "Enlargement of Self."
For the unedited version, see the Further Reading
section below.
- How would you describe Russell's practical
person?
- The practical mind is a Philistine: a person deficient in
liberal culture, according to Russell: someone whose interests
are material and commonplace.
- The instinctive man is practical as is the man of
self-assertion described later. He is not interested in
providing for society and not interested in "goods for
the mind."
- His friendships are "friendships of utility," not
as Aristotle describes "friendships of the good."
The practical person is interested in people for what they
can do for him.
- The practical person is more interested in "the
answer" rather than how one obtains an answer.
- He has a "them against us" mentality. E.g.,
Vince Lombardi, the well-known American football coach, is
famously known for saying, "Winning isn't everything,
it's the only thing" and as well, he stated,
"Show me a good loser, and I'll show you a loser."
Contrast Lombardi's attitude with, for example, with Leo
Buscaglia's prescription to "celebrate life" and
"develop a passion for many things."
- Why not live one's life as a practical person?
- The practical person recognizes material needs; he is less
aware of goods of the mind. For example, philosophy can give
a different kind of value to life—not something
superadded to material value, but a value intrinsically
different. Consider what Socrates said about "tending
your soul." as a means to a life of excellence.
- The philosophical mind has an awareness that goes beyond
the daily round to an understanding of life and the world.
- Generally the practical person does not recognize basic
truths about everyday life such as…
- In general, choices cannot justified by their consequences.
- Perception is not reality. How things appear to be is
less important than how they are.
- The excuse that "things turned out all right" is
not always sufficient. Often, the practical person is unaware
of true consequences.
- You can be right for the world, even though the world is
not right for you.
- The practical person often does not notice the world and
the people in it because of his own worries that tend to
feed upon themselves.
- What are the goals of philosophy?
- First, Russell looks at the relation between science and
philosophy in the past as a question which must be answered
first.
- Consider the following sketch of the origins of the sciences
from persons who were considered at the time to be
philosophers but are now considered to be some of the
founders of the various sciences.
Philosophical Origins of the Sciences
Date |
Figure |
Discipline |
Work |
582?-500? BC |
Pythagoras |
Mathematics |
Pythogorean theorem; geometry |
408-355 BC |
Eudoxus |
Mathematics |
irrationals, number theory |
about 300 BC |
Euclid |
Mathematics |
Elements (300 BC) |
490?-430 BC |
Empedocles |
Biology |
On Nature: theory of evolution |
384-322 BC |
Aristotle |
Biology |
De Anima (350 BC) |
460?-377? BC |
Hippocrates |
Biology |
Airs, Waters, and Places (400 BC) |
1571-1630 |
Kepler |
Astronomy |
Astronomia nova (1609) |
1473-1543 |
Copernicus |
Astronomy |
De Revolutionibus Orbium Coelestium (1543) |
1546-1601 |
Brahe |
Astronomy |
Epitome of Copernican Astronomy (1618-1621) |
1564-1642 |
Galileo |
Physics |
The Starry Messenger (1610) |
1642-1727 |
Newton |
Physics |
Philosophiæ Naturalis Principia Mathematica (1687) |
1743-1794 |
Lavoisier |
Chemistry |
Traité Élémentaire de Chimie (1789) |
766-1844 |
Dalton |
Chemistry |
New System of Chemical Philosophy (1808) |
1798-1857 |
Comte |
Sociology |
Course of Positive Philosophy (1830-1842) |
1806-1873 |
Mill |
Sociology |
Logic of the Moral Sciences (1843) |
1858-1917 |
Durkheim |
Sociology |
Suicide: A Study in Sociology (1897) |
|
Wundt |
Psychology |
System der Philosophie (1889) |
1842-1910 |
James |
Psychology |
Principles of Psychology (1890) |
1849-1936 |
Pavlov |
Psychology |
Conditioned Reflexes (1926) |
- Hence, as soon as definite knowledge concerning any subject
becomes possible, this subject draws its own skilled
practitioners. The subject leaves philosophy and becomes a
science.
- Questions with definite answers come from fruitful
presuppositions and are placed in the sciences. Philosophy,
like science, aims at knowledge, but that knowledge can only
come to fruition in another age in a science born from
philosophical inquiry.
- Consider the example that the distinction between moral
philosophy and natural philosophy was the main division of the
curriculum in many universities as late as the beginning of
the twentieth century.
- Consider also the terminal degrees given in many different
fields of knowledge such as literature, science, music, and
so-forth are PhD's—i.e., Doctor of Philosophy.
- What does Russell think is the central value of
philosophical inquiry?
- Russell gives the examples of philosophical questions in
the following passage:
- "Has the universe any unity of plan or purpose, or
is it a fortuitous concourse of atoms? Is consciousness a
permanent part of the universe, giving hope of indefinite
growth in wisdom, or is it a transitory accident on a small
planet on which life must ultimately become impossible? Are
good and evil of importance to the universe or only to man?
Such questions are asked by philosophy, and variously
answered by various philosophers."
- Notice that these questions exemplify the main divisions of
philosophy studied previously in these notes:
- Russell's questions "Has the universe any unity of
plan or purpose? Is consciousness a permanent part of
the universe?" is a metaphysical or
ontological question.
- Russell's question "Is there hope of indefinite
growth in wisdom?" belongs to epistemology.
- And, finally, the question "Are good and evil
subjective?" represents the divisions of axiology
which includes the subdivisions of ethics and
æsthetics.
- To attempt to Russell's questions we would investigate these
main fields of philosophical inquiry:
- Ontology (Metaphysics): the study of what is really real.
- Epistemology: the study of knowledge—its scope and
limits.
- Axiology: the study of values.
- Ethics: the study of the good and what constitutes a
good life.
- Æesthetics: the study of the beautiful.
- As far as the main value of philosophy, Russell says philosophy
seeks knowledge like science, but is different from science.
- Recognizing that there is no absolute certainty,
philosophy shows unsuspected possibilities about matters
of fact. Consider, for example, Norwood
Russell Hanson's question: "Do Kepler and Tycho see the same thing in
the east at dawn?"
- Hence, philosophy increases the possibility of knowledge
through the reduction of dogmatism.
- Russell says the chief value is the "greatness of
objects which it contemplates." Thus it is reasonable to
infer the object of epistemology is truth, that of
ontology is reality, that of ethics is the good,
that of æsthetics is beauty.
- Thus, philosophy gives freedom from narrow and practical aims:
an escape from the daily round.
- Characterize the instinctive individual.
- The instinctive person lives in a prison of his own
making—much like an animal aware only of what it senses
and feels.
- The instinctive person tends not to look beyond what is before
him at the moment.
- Being unaware of the larger world can put our private world
in ruins when we do not think about the meaning of change and
cause.
- What is "enlargement of self"?
- "Enlargement of self" is Russell's expression for
the person of liberal culture, wide interests, reflection,
understanding, and self-motivation.
- Russell's phrase "a share in infinity" denotes the
approach of synoptic philosophy.
- Consider the following example: What, specific essential
information could an expert in each the following fields of
knowledge advise about the purchase of floor covering in
the newly proposed science building? The person of wide interests
would be able to state three or four crucial factors for
each of the following fields: anthropology, art, astronomy, botany, chemistry,
communications, computer science, ecology, economics, geography,
geology, history, linguistics, literature, mathematics,
music, physical education, physics, political science,
psychology, religion, sociology, theatre arts.
- Enlargement of self takes an objective view to escape from the
instinctive circle of the daily round. When you see yourself
as a process, you see yourself developing as you will be.
(E.g., why are beginners afraid to make mistakes?
After all, if one did not make mistakes, one would not be
a beginner.)
- Do not define yourself in reaction to what others say
you must do: self-reliance
- Pursue an interest for its own sake—not what it can do
for you. Recognize that there are many possibilities for
solutions—not just the pragmatic or dogmatic "right
or wrong" dichotomy.
- Being motivated to seek knowledge leads to a richer view
of the world.
- By way of contrast, the way of self-assertion views the
world as a means to its own end and sees the world in
terms of itself: pragmatic, dogmatic, instinctive, and
direct.
- On this view, getting results or getting the right
answer is more important that understanding how
such things are accomplished.
- The practical mind leads to a limited and impoverished
view of the world—there is a lack of creativity
and a lack of play with things.
- If one is self-assertive, then sometimes minor slights
are taken personally. There might be other reasons for
an individual's behavior that do not involve you.
- Enlargement of self does not shape such dualisms as
the "them against us" mentality.
- How does philosophical thinking relate to living
and acting in the world? Suggest some examples.
- The key to this question is "impartial contemplation."
Taking sides in interpersonal almost always involves a
dogmatic position.
- Our external physical states such as money, job, car, make
little difference if one is reaching one's life goals. The
main concern may be happiness vs. misery rather than a
question of being an auto mechanic or a corporation executive.
- The philosophic mind is open and nonjudgmental. Such a person
does not expect other people or situations to change just to
fit what that person wants in order for that person to be happy.
- The philosophic mind has the recognition that it could be wrong
in any situation.
- The Wikipedia entry on Bertrand
Russell is recommended for an overview of Russell's
life and works.
“The nature of mind precludes any discovery or deduction,
whether physical or moral, until experiments have been made, or
proofs investigated; and the progress of science during the last
most conclusively teaches us, that the last attainment of a
philosophic mind, as the result of all its inductive enquiries,
is the poser of forming a simple proposition. To this end, how did
Newton toil, that he might trace the demonstrations which enabled
him to assert the laws of the planetary system!” Rev.
Richard W. Dickinson, “On the Origin of Our Idea Respecting
God,” in Literary and Theological Review (New York:
Franklin Knight) (December, 1835) Vol. II, No. VIII, 568.
[an error occurred while processing this directive]
This page last updated 12/20/09
© 2006 Licensed under the GFDL
|