Cite Entry
September 9 2024
07:16 EDT
Jacob's Ladder, Biblioteca Chemica Curiosa, 1702, Library of Congress
SITE SEARCH ENGINE
|
Introduction to Philosophy
Thomas Aquinas, "The Argument from Gradation"
Abstract: Thomas' Argument from Gradation for the existence
of God is outlined and briefly clarified. Some standard objections to that
argument are listed.
- Thomas' Argument from Gradation begins with the empirical observation of
different degrees of goodness in different kinds of things in the world.
Hence, this argument is actually an à posteriori argument, and
the conclusion is not claimed to follow with absolute certainty.
- Summary of the Argument from Gradation:
- There are different degrees of goodness in different things.
- There are different degrees of being in different things—the more being,
the more goodness. (The notion of the
Great Chain of Being
is being presupposed.)
- For there to be degrees of being at all, there must be something
which has being in the highest degree.
- Therefore, a Being in the Highest Degree or Perfect Being exists.
- Some of the difficulties in understanding the Argument from Gradation
are based on the following suppositions briefly described here with
examples.
- Degrees of Being. In Plato's and Plotinus' philosophy, the
universe is conceived as an ascent from less real to more real. The
highest Form is the Form of the Good, the ens perfectissimum.
In the Republic,
Plato explains four levels of existence: (1) shadows, reflections,
dreams, (2) perceptions, sensations, images, (3) lower forms
of science, and (4) higher forms of mathematics and the intelligible
form of the good. Levels (1) and (2) are the changing, impermanent, visible realm, and Levels
(3) and (4) are the real, permanent, intelligible realm. Similarly,
Plato's metaphor of the sun explains the Form of the Good
(representing God or ultimate reality) as illuminating the perceptual world
of becoming and passing away. In Aristotle's scala naturae or
ladder of nature, objects in the world range from inanimate matter to plants,
invertebrates, and finally human beings according to their
formal factor.
- Goodness is a quality of objects. Thomas' presupposition makes
goodness a natural property like pleasure or evolutionary fitness. Instead,
good seems to be an intentional or purposive property of human beings. On a planet, without
human habitation, the values "good" and "bad" would have
no meaning.
- The Great Chain of Being. From the notion of
Jacob's Ladder,
where the rungs go from the materialistic world (rung by rung, through
prayer) to union with God as well as the notion of Homer's
"golden chain"
linking the earth and the heavens, The Great Chain of Being is a
common theme in Western Philosophy. Even John Locke, for example, in his
Essay
speaks of the links in nature which "ascend upward from us toward infinite
perfection,as we see they gradually descend from us downwards." As
Pope
writes …
“Vast chain of being, which from God began,
Natures æthereal, human angel, man,
Beast, bird, fish, insect! what no eye can see,
No glass can reach! from Infinite to thee,
From thee to Nothing!…”
The Great
Chain of Being extends from unformed inorganic matter to man to God. For example,
a rabbit is higher than a snake and an angel is higher than a person—there is
a movement to more form and complexity as one ascends up the chain.
- Summary list of common objections to Thomas' Argument from Gradation:
- Goodness is a moral quality—it's a function of human purpose and
intention, not a "kind" of being. As
Spinoza argues in his Ethics…
As for the terms good and bad, they indicate no positive quality in things
regarded in themselves, but are merely modes of thinking, or notions which
we form from the comparison of thing one with another. Thus one and the
same thing can be at the same time good, bad, and indifferent. For instance,
music is good for him that is melancholy, bad for him that mourns; for
him this is deaf, it is neither good nor bad.
For example, in biological taxonomy the hierarchial system of classification
does not represent a "chain of goodness," but a kind of niche based
success or fitness.
- Difficulties in measuring goodness. How do we measure the goodness
of different things? What could be the standard of comparison of two different
kinds of things? Aren't some things better and are less complex that other
things? Which is better a rose or a crocus? Are the levels of being
and goodness a difference of degree or a difference of kind?
- Voltaire notes that the distance between God and the next good being would
be an infinite distance.
- Similarly, Samuel Johnson points out the incommunensurability between the
infinite and the highest finite begin. He points as well to the paradox
resulting from the apparent infinite divisibility between two order of existence
giving rise to other orders of existence.
- Finally, comparisons can be made among things without presupposing
maximum values to those things. There seems to be no good reason to assume
with Thomas that "…the maximum
in any genus is the cause of all in that genus,…" Simply
because things exist in degrees, it does not follow that something exists
in the maximum or minimum of degree. (For example, there is no greatest
integer.) Being is not a genus; consequently, to
say that being in the highest degree must follow is to be subject to
Russell's Paradox:
the problem of the set of sets which are not
members of themselves.
- There would be many different things (gods) who are the maximum
of the various genera. As Thomas writes, "… there is
something which is truest, something best, something noblest…"
The various genera would have to be somehow combined rather than have the
maximum of the true, the maximum of the best, and the maximum of the
noblest—three different maximums or perfections.
- The Problem of Evil How can we account
for a Perfect God creating a world in which innocent children suffer? How do
we account for the non-moral evil in the world such as flood, hurricane, and
earthquake? (Aquinas replies, "This is part of the infinite goodness of
God, that He should allow evil to exist, and out of it produce good.")
- Even if Thomas' concepts of being and goodness were intelligible, there
could be equally plausible candidates for being in the highest degree:
nature, matter, existence, or even limited deities.
- Argument from Polar Concepts. If Thomas can argue that "for there
to be degrees of goodness at all, there must be something which has goodness in
the highest degree," it would also seem to follow that analogously there
would be degrees of badness or evil. For there to be degrees of evil at all,
it would seem to follow that there must be something which has evil to the highest
degree. Can we know what absolute good is without supposing that there is an absolute
bad? Can we conceive of one without the other?
- Couldn't the same argument be used to conclude that an
all-powerful evil being exists?
- Augustine would conclude by analogy that God illumes existence. Just as
shadow is the absence of sunlight, evil is the absence of goodness. Hence,
evil is nothing positive in itself, it is merely the absence of goodness.
Thus, absolute evil is nonexistence.
- Even if the Argument from Gradation were correct, Thomas would have to solve the
problem that with these five ways he is proving five gods with five
different properties. At a minimum, it would be necessary to prove that all five
beings are actually the same being.
Further Reading:
- “Chain
of Being” The idea of the Chain of Being or scala
naturae and objections are traced in some detail through the
history of philosophy from Plato's use of Forms, Christian theology,
and the natural sciences by Lia Formigari in the Dictionary
of the History of Ideas maintained by the Electronic Text
Center at the University of Virginia Library.
- “Hierarchy
and Order” The notion levels or degrees of existence as
an ubiquitous idea in the history of Western philosophy, religion,
literature, and science is examined by C. A. Patrides in this
article from the Dictionary
of the History of Ideas maintained by the Electronic Text
Center at the University of Virginia Library.
“The chain of being assembles all beings in a comprehensive
association which specifies every particular being with the
attribution of a relative, at once and indifferently ethical and
ontological, position with respect to other beings. This assembly is
a scale bounded by its extremities, the topmost of which is endowed
with absolute value and the lowest of which is somewhat like the obverse
the first and its mirror image. The topmost point of the scale,
which is occupied by God, is the one in possession of normative
positivity in its absolute fullness, positively as ethical norm and as
ontological value. All that is not God is regarded according to
the neo-Platonic scheme of things: as degrees of privation. Full
existence, absolute goodness and eternity (as distinct from
sempiternity), are attributable solely to God; apart from Him, existence
and value are relative matters. This is the meaning of the saying
which Abū Hayyān al-Tawḥīdī (d. after
400/1009) attributes to Abū Sulaimām al-Sijistānī
(d. after 391/1001), that ‘evil is nothingness … while
good is being,’ a saying that seems to duplicate many others
of the same import.” Aziz Al-Azmeth et al. Arabic Thought
and Islamic Societies (London: Routledge, 1986), 2.
[an error occurred while processing this directive]
This page last updated 12/20/09
© 2006 Licensed under the GFDL
|