Cite Entry
September 9 2024
07:30 EDT
Blaise Pascal, painting by Philippe de Champangne
SITE SEARCH ENGINE
|
Introduction to Philosophy
Pascal's Wager
Abstract: Since Pascal does not think a
sound argument can be given for God's existence, he proposes a
pragmatically persuasive consideration.
- According to Pascal, how much can be known about
God?
- Reconstruct Pascal's Wager as carefully as possible.
- Explain whether you consider Pascal's Wager a proof
of God's existence or not?
- What major objections can you construct to the Wager?
Can the objections be countered?
- Clarify the meaning of Pascal's sentence, "The
heart has its reasons which reason does not know."
- Blaise Pascal (1632-1662).
- Several biographical points should be briefly mentioned.
- With no formal education, Pascal studied languages at home until
he became fascinated with Euclid's Elements.
- At sixteen Pascal wrote an important essay on the geometry of conic
sections for a group of mathematicians who later formed part of the
French Academy.
- He studied and made contributions to the physics of gases and
liquids.
- By correspondence with Fermat, Pascal helped form the origin of
probability theory. His final work solved several important problems
raised by the cycloid: a mathemathical curve formed by the path
taken by a point on the circumference of a circle as it rolls along
a straight line.
- The Pensées from which "The Wager" is taken
is a collection of fragments reconstructed by editors who might not
accurately reflect the original writing of Pascal.
- William James's thesis in "The
Will to Believe" is similar to Pascal's Wager; even so for
James, Pascal's Wager would not constitute a momentous option and
does not represent a method of how belief is established.
- The Wager
- Notes are arranged in response to the questions stated above in
reference to Pascal's chapter
"The
Wager" from Pensées in Reading for Philosophical Inquiry.
- According to Pascal, how much can be known about
God?
- God is so completely different from us that there is no way for us
to comprehend him.
- We can know that God is, but we cannot know what God is.
- Ordinary human descriptions are futile and paradoxical when applied
beyond the bounds of everyday application when we say God is
all-powerful, all-good, and all-knowing. These predicates are beyond
our experience.
- Reconstruct Pascal's Wager as carefully as
possible.
- Pascal does not think that the atheist or the believer would be
convinced by his Wager. Instead, he directs the Wager to the
curious and unconvinced.
- I have a choice: either first I believe God exists or second I
do not believe God exists.
- First, if I believe God exists, and God in fact does exist, then I
will gain infinite happiness. However, if I believe God exists, and
God in fact does not exist, then I will have no payoff.
- Second, if I do not believe God exists, and God in fact does exist,
then I will gain infinite pain. However, if I believe God does not
exist, and God in fact does not exist, then I will have no payoff.
- Thus, I have everything to gain and nothing to lose by believing in
God, and I have everything to lose and nothing to gain by not believing
in God. On these grounds, one would be foolish not to believe.
- Explain whether you consider Pascal's Wager a proof
of God's existence or not?
- I come to have faith in God by "acting as if I believed." I,
in effect, change my attitude, not my reason.
- In much the same manner as Tolstoy
would write several centuries later, Pascal indicates we learn from
those who believe and become like them. As a result of the Wager,
we have nothing to lose and everything to gain.
- By rational decision theory, one can calculate the expected return of a
payoff. Suppose I wonder whether I should enter the Family Publisher's
Sweepstakes with a possible payoff of 20 million dollars. I look in the fine print
and see that the chance of winning the payoff is 1 in 450 million. I can
calculate my "expected" return by doing a thought-experiment.
Suppose I enter the contest an indefinite number of times; I will win
on the average the amount calculated by the following formula:
[the probability of winning] X [the payoff] = [the
expected return].
- So, doing the math ...
[1 / 450,000,000] X [$2,000,000] = [$0.0044] or less than a half of a penny.
- Obviously, if I return my entry by mail I would normally lose money because
of the cost of the stamp, the opportunity cost of my time, and, among other
things, the shoe leather used on the way to the post office.
- With God's promise of an afterlife, however, the payoff is so large that
the expected return makes it almost irrational not to believe, even if
the probability were low. Even so, of course, there is no certainty there would be a
payoff.
- The everyday beliefs we act on are the things we believe the strongest.
We never bother to prove these beliefs. We do not try to prove the existence
of the external world, that the sun will rise tomorrow, that the floor will
remain under our feet, or that we are awake.
- It is little matter that we can, or cannot, prove these beliefs, so likewise,
it is little matter that we prove God's existence. We simply assume life will
go on, without proof; otherwise, it would be disastrous to our everyday
existence if we were occupied with proving these ordinary things.
- In sum, Pascal's Wager is not intended to be a philosophical proof; the
Wager is just intented as a persuasive, pragmatic consideration directed
to the agnostic.
- What major objections can you construct to the Wager?
Can the objections be countered?
- Two main objections are often raised to Pascal's Wager.
- (1) To believe in God simply for the payoff is the wrong motive for
belief. Such self-seeking individuals would not properly serve the
Deity.
- (2) In order to be sure of a payoff, an individual would not know
which God or gods to believe in to cover the conditions of the wager.
Would the Wager also hold for Zeus, Odin,or Mithra? One would have to
believe in all gods to be sure, but if there were only one God in
fact, then this strategy would defeat itself.
- Pascal could argue objection (1) isn't about subjective intentions;
it's about objective probabilities.
- Pascal could argue for objection (2) the different conceptions of
different religions could refer to the same God.
- Clarify the meaning of Pascal's sentence, "The
heart has its reasons which reason does not know."
- Human beings live not by reason alone. Without heart, feeling,
emotion, life would lose its value.
- Our uniqueness as a species might be the ability to think, but let
not that blind ourselves to the fact that our whole value individually
or as a group is not in reason alone.
- W.
W. Rouse Ball points out with respect of the Wager: "Pascal
made an illegitimate use of the new theory in the seventh chapter of
his Pensées. In effect, he puts his argument that, as the value of
eternal happiness must be infinite, then, even if the probability of
a religious life ensuring eternal happiness be very small, still the
expectation (which is measured by the product of the two) must be of
sufficient magnitude to make it worth while to be religious. The
argument, if worth anything, would apply equally to any religion
which promised eternal happiness to those who accepted its doctrines.
If any conclusion may be drawn from the statement, it is the
undersirability of applying mathematics to questions of morality of
which some of the data are necessarily outside the range of an exact
science. It is only fair to add that no one had more contempt than
Pascal for those who changes their opinions according to the prospect
of material benefit, and this isolated passage is at variance with
the spirit of his writings."
Further Reading:
- Blaise
Pascal (1623-1662). A mathematical biography transcribed from W. W. Rouse Ball's
A Short Account of the History of Mathematics by D.R. Wilkins.
- Decision Theory: The
Wikipedia's entry article summarizing some of the major approaches
to choice under uncertainty including mention of Pascal together with extensive
references is an excellent starting place to learn something of decision theory.
- Pascal's Wager. A clear and
precise summary of the cluster of issues surrounding the Wager including
super-dominance, expectation, genuine option, and paradox-objections by
Paul Saka in The Internet Encyclopedia of Philosophy
- Pascal's Wager:
A thorough account of Pascal's Wager including the argument from superdominance and
probabilistic expected value together with objections and extensive bibliography is
provided by Alan Hájek in the Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy.
- Religious
Language. A student handout by Scott Moore of Baylor University summarily
lists some of the major philosophical approaches to the problem of reference
in religious language.
“Pascal's reasoning may have been theologically simplistic, but
it was mathematically intriguing. It illustrated the kind of reasoning that
goes into calculation the ‘mathematical expectation’ of an
economic decision—you miltiply he probability of an outcome by
the value of that outcome. The reaitonal choice is the decision that
computes to give the highest expected value. Pascal's wager is often
cited as the earliest example of a math-based approach to decision
theory.” Tom Siegfried, A Beautiful Math: John Nash, Game Theory,
and the Modern Quest for a Code of Nature (Washington, D. C.: Joseph
Henry Press, 2006), 198.
[an error occurred while processing this directive]
This page last updated 12/20/09
© 2006 Licensed under the GFDL
|